War and Peace
a level on which the question itself cannot exist. In our time the majority of so-called advanced people—that is, the crowd of ignoramuses—have taken the work of the naturalists who deal with one side of the question for a solution of the whole problem.
They say and write and print that the
soul and freedom do not exist, for the life of man is expressed by muscular movements and muscular movements are conditioned by the activity of the nerves; the
soul and free
will do not exist because at an unknown period of time we sprang from the apes. They say this, not at all suspecting that thousands of years ago that same law of
necessity which with such ardor they are now trying to prove by physiology and comparative zoology was not merely acknowledged by all the religions and all the thinkers, but has never been denied. They do not see that the role of the natural sciences in this
matter is merely to serve as an instrument for the illumination of one side of it. For the
fact that, from the point of view of
observation,
reason and the
will are merely secretions of the brain, and that man following the general law may have developed from lower animals at some unknown period of time, only explains from a fresh side the truth admitted thousands of years ago by all the religious and philosophic theories—that from the point of view of
reason man is
subject to the law of
necessity; but it does not advance by a hair’s breadth the solution of the question, which has another, opposite, side, based on the
consciousness of freedom.
If men descended from the apes at an unknown period of time, that is as comprehensible as that they were made from a handful of earth at a certain period of time (in the first case the unknown
quantity is the time, in the second case it is the origin); and the question of how man’s
consciousness of freedom is to be reconciled with the law of
necessity to which he is
subject cannot be solved by comparative physiology and zoology, for in a frog, a rabbit, or an ape, we can observe only the muscular nervous activity, but in man we observe
consciousness as well as the muscular and nervous activity.
The naturalists and their followers, thinking they can solve this question, are like plasterers set to plaster one side of the walls of a
church who, availing themselves of the absence of the chief superintendent of the work, should in an access of zeal plaster over the windows, icons, woodwork, and still unbuttressed walls, and should be delighted that from their point of view as plasterers, everything is now so smooth and regular.
FOR THE SOLUTION of the question of free
will or inevitability, history has this advantage over other branches of knowledge in which the question is dealt with, that for history this question does not refer to the
essence of man’s free
will but its manifestation in the past and under certain conditions.
In regard to this question, history stands to the other sciences as experimental science stands to
abstract science.
The
subject for history is not man’s
will itself but our presentation of it.
And so for history, the insoluble mystery presented by the incompatibility of free
will and inevitability does not exist as it does for theology,
ethics, and philosophy. History surveys a presentation of man’s life in which the
union of these two contradictions has already taken place.
In actual life each historic event, each human action, is very clearly and definitely understood without any
sense of
contradiction, although each event presents itself as partly free and partly compulsory.
To solve the question of how freedom and
necessity are combined and what constitutes the
essence of these two conceptions, the
philosophy of history can and should follow a path contrary to that taken by other sciences. Instead of first defining the conceptions of freedom and inevitability in themselves, and then ranging the
phenomena of life under those definitions, history should deduce a definition of the conception of freedom and inevitability themselves from the immense
quantity of
phenomena of which it is cognizant and that always appear dependent on these two elements.
Whatever presentation of the activity of many men or of an
individual we may consider, we always regard it as the result partly of man’s free
will and partly of the law of inevitability.
Whether we speak of the migration of the peoples and the incursions of the barbarians, or of the decrees of Napoleon III, or of someone’s action an hour ago in choosing one direction out of several for his walk, we are
unconscious of any
contradiction. The
degree of freedom and inevitability governing the actions of these people is clearly defined for us.
Our conception of the
degree of freedom often varies according to differences in the point of view from which we regard the event, but every human action appears to us as a certain combination of freedom and inevitability. In every action we examine we see a certain measure of freedom and a certain measure of inevitability. And always the
more freedom we see in any action the less inevitability do we perceive, and the
more inevitability the less freedom.
The proportion of freedom to inevitability decreases and increases according to the point of view from which the action is regarded, but their
relation is always one of inverse proportion.
A sinking man who clutches at another and drowns him; or a hungry mother exhausted by feeding her baby, who steals some food; or a man trained to discipline who on duty at the word of command kills a defenseless man—seem less guilty, that is, less free and
more subject to the law of
necessity, to one who knows the circumstances in which these people were placed, and
more free to one who does not know that the man was himself drowning, that the mother was hungry, that the soldier was in the ranks, and so on. Similarly a man who committed a murder twenty years ago and has since lived peaceably and harmlessly in society seems less guilty and his action
more due to the law of inevitability, to someone who considers his action after twenty years have elapsed than to one who examined it the day after it was committed. And in the same way every action of an insane, intoxicated, or highly excited man appears less free and
more inevitable to one who knows the mental condition of him who committed the action, and seems
more free and less inevitable to one who does not know it. In all these cases the conception of freedom is increased or diminished and the conception of compulsion is correspondingly decreased or increased, according to the point of view from which the action is regarded. So that the greater the conception of
necessity the smaller the conception of freedom and
vice versa.
Religion, the common
sense of mankind, the science of
jurisprudence, and history itself understand alike this
relation between
necessity and freedom.
All cases without exception in which our conception of freedom and
necessity is increased and diminished depend on three considerations:
(1) The
relation to the external world of the man who commits the deeds.
(2) His
relation to time.
(3) His
relation to the causes leading to the action.
The first consideration is the clearness of our perception of the man’s
relation to the external world and the greater or lesser clearness of our
understanding of the definite position occupied by the man in
relation to everything coexisting with him. This is what makes it evident that a drowning man is less free and
more subject to
necessity than one standing on dry ground, and that makes the actions of a man closely
connected with others in a thickly populated district, or of one bound by family, official, or business duties, seem certainly less free and
more subject to
necessity than those of a man living in solitude and seclusion.
If we consider a man alone, apart from his
relation to everything around him, each action of his seems to us free. But if we see his
relation to anything around him, if we see his connection with anything whatever—with a man who speaks to him, a book he reads, the work on which he is engaged, even with the air he breathes or the light that falls on the things about him—we see that each of these circumstances has an influence on him and controls at least some side of his activity. And the
more we perceive of these influences the
more our conception of his freedom diminishes and the
more our conception of the
necessity that weighs on him increases.
The second consideration is the
more or less evident time
relation of the man to the world and the clearness of our perception of the place the man’s action occupies in time. That is the ground which makes the fall of the first man, resulting in the production of the human race, appear evidently less free than a man’s entry into marriage today. It is the
reason why the life and activity of people who lived centuries ago and are
connected with me in time cannot seem to me as free as the life of a contemporary, the consequences of which are still unknown to me.
The
degree of our conception of freedom or inevitability depends in this respect on the greater or lesser lapse of time between the performance of the action and our
judgment of it.
If I examine an act I performed a moment ago in approximately